One of the most frequently cited platitudes regarding the purpose of contemporary schools is that they must help our young people “to think critically.” Not only does the question about the precise content of this thinking go unquestioned, but more curiously is inquiring whether such thinking is possible at all. Is it possible that, due to the rise of certain social and cultural conditions, and especially technology and social media, that we may in fact be setting up, in an ironic way, modes of “critical thinking” that actually lead towards the destruction of thought?

At the conclusion of his 1989 essay “The End of History,” the social scientist Francis Fukuyama made the following remarks about the existential condition of citizens at the end of history:

            The end of history will be a very sad time. The struggle for recognition, the willingness to risk one’s life for a purely abstract goal, the worldwide struggle that called forth daring,                            courage, imagination, and idealism, will be replaced by economic calculation, the endless            solving of technical problems, environmental concerns, and the satisfaction of                                            sophisticated consumer demands. In the post-historical period there will be neither art                               nor philosophy, just the perpetual catering of the museum of human history.

To speak of “the end of history” does not mean that history itself will cease. Instead, Fukuyama means to convey the rise of a social and intellectual worldview that conceives of history as having given modern liberal democracy to the world. My contention is that this “end of history” perspective is predominantly concerned with an account of freedom that too often lacks substantive moral, philosophical, and even religious content. Freedom is a necessary, but not sufficient, condition for the building of culture (which is one of the fundamental goals of an education).

The 19th century social philosopher Alexis de Tocqueville made a rather stunning, and prophetic, observation in this regard, one that goes contrary to lamentations of contemporary “academic freedom.”

            Intellectual authority will be different, but it will not be less; and so far am I from                                        believing that it will disappear that I augur that it might readily become too great…I see                              very clearly two tendencies in equality: one brings the mind of each man toward new                             thoughts, and the other would willingly induce it to give up thinking (Democracy in                                 America, 410).

In Tocqueville’s estimation, once social conditions foster a level of universal equality, there    becomes a disposition to distrust once-established cultural forms of authority. To use Crawford’s language, we would call local and cultural forms of authority jigs. As a result, Tocqueville      argues, “more and more it is opinion that leads the world,” and opinion will transform into a “sort of religion whose prophet will be the majority.” It is necessary to consider not only where such a position came from, but also its philosophical presuppositions as expressed and lived in America. Thankfully, Tocqueville does this by getting two birds with one stone:

          I think that in no country in the civilized world is less attention paid to philosophy than in      the United States…Nevertheless it is easy to perceive that almost all the inhabitants of the                                 United States conduct their understanding in the same manner, and govern it by the same                          rules; that is to say, that without ever having taken the trouble to define the rules of a                              philosophical method, they are in possession of one, common to the whole people. To                                evade the bondage of system and habit, of family maxims, class opinions, and, in some                                    degree, of national prejudices; to accept tradition only as a means of information, and                                 existing facts only as a lesson used in doing otherwise, and doing better; to seek the                                   reason of things for one’s self, and in one’s self alone..America is therefore one of the                                countries in the world where philosophy is least studied, and where the precepts of                              Descartes are best applied (Democracy in America, 403).

Connected to the judgment above regarding intellectual authority, Tocqueville perceived a      specific American tendency “to mistrust the judgment of others, and to seek the light of truth nowhere but in their own understandings.” As a result, “everyone then attempts to be his own sufficient guide, and makes it his boast to form his own opinions on all subjects. Men are no longer bound together by ideas, but by interests; and it would seem as if human opinions were reduced to a sort of intellectual dust, scattered on every side, unable to collect, unable to cohere” (Democracy in America, 406).

It is crucial to highlight certain observations here which, although distinct, are nonetheless interrelated. These points will be further explored during this course, but it is helpful to touch upon them in our introduction. The first observation is a historical one about the 17th century French philosopher Rene Descartes. Descartes held that human sensation (touch, smell, taste, sight, and hearing) was often deceptive, and thus could not be trusted. He concluded that the only certitude we could have was that humans are “thinking things,” simply minds.

Descartes’ epistemology (his view of how we come to know) is similar to that of the British political philosopher John Locke. In Locke’s political and philosophical writings, he argues that the human mind is not capable of grasping the real order of nature or the essences of things. Rather, what the human mind knows are simply the mind’s own mental representations. Thus, knowledge is not ordered to an external object, or set of objects, but instead towards its own ideas.

According to both Descartes and Locke, we do not have access to reality, but only to the ideas in our minds. Philosophy since that time has been continually             concerned with the problema pontis (“the problem of the bridge), and whether there is any bridge between the mind and the real world.

Second, when philosophy or the primacy of thought and reason has been cut asunder and rejected, what follows then is an elevation of the practical order. We no longer conceive of ourselves as truth seekers, but as those who must seek to transform the world through political and social action. What takes precedence gradually becomes that of our interests and desires. Instead of             relying on the formation of our judgments and ideas within a broader community, we “seek the light of truth nowhere but in our own understandings,” as Tocqueville shows. Truth is not                   something to which we are naturally ordered and must discover, according to this view; now, truth is one of self-creation, and our isolated selves alone are its arbiters.

Finally, with this loss of philosophy, and the predominance of knowing only our own mental representations, comes an inability to “collect” and “cohere.” By this, Tocqueville seems to mean that all the data and information we receive can not be ordered into a synthesis or whole that helps us to make sense of it all. Rather, we only observe information and “parts,” incapable of seeing there relation to any order beyond that.

Descartes goes on to draw out the implications of this point. By rejecting the speculative               philosophy of Aristotle and Plato, Descartes has sought to elevate a practical philosophy             grounded in no order other than that of human action. Instead of viewing human beings as             receivers and nurturers of a created order, those who first seek to understand, Descartes initiates a primary focus on activity that renders “ourselves, as it were, masters and possessors of nature” (Discourse on Method, VI, 35).  

Let us return to Fukuyama’s judgment about the condition of citizens at the end of history. He argues that it will be a “sad time.” Why, though, would such a condition be sad? Consider the quote from the beginning by Fukayama:

            The end of history will be a very sad time. The struggle for recognition, the willingness to risk one’s life for a purely abstract goal, the worldwide struggle that called forth daring,                            courage, imagination, and idealism, will be replaced by economic calculation, the endless            solving of technical problems, environmental concerns, and the satisfaction of                                            sophisticated consumer demands. In the post-historical period there will be neither art                               nor philosophy, just the perpetual catering of the museum of human history.

Is genuine thinking and reasoning possible in contemporary American democracy? The answer it seems, at least according to Tocqueville and Fukayama, is that it is not possible without the       recovery of philosophy. Perhaps we could call this recovery of philosophy something akin to what Matthew Crawford calls “an ethics of attention.” Such an approach connects human beings to truth, about themselves, the world, and our place in it. A society full of citizens that denies this may tend toward worship in the only religion left, namely, the despotism of their own opinion.

All papers are written by ENL (US, UK, AUSTRALIA) writers with vast experience in the field. We perform a quality assessment on all orders before submitting them.

Do you have an urgent order?  We have more than enough writers who will ensure that your order is delivered on time. 

We provide plagiarism reports for all our custom written papers. All papers are written from scratch.

24/7 Customer Support

Contact us anytime, any day, via any means if you need any help. You can use the Live Chat, email, or our provided phone number anytime.

We will not disclose the nature of our services or any information you provide to a third party.

Assignment Help Services
Money-Back Guarantee

Get your money back if your paper is not delivered on time or if your instructions are not followed.

We Guarantee the Best Grades
Assignment Help Services